ON
PEIKOFF’S ‘FACT AND VALUE’
by
Merlin Jetton July 27, 1989
The
series of articles by Peter Schwartz, David Kelley, and Leonard
Peikoff was both interesting and disappointing to read. It amazes me
that such a heated exchange could arise from the mere event of David
Kelley making a speech.
I
have come to expect such behavior from Schwartz. He has a history of
making straw men and burning them. He sometimes makes bizarre
judgments. He did that in this instance, operating under the
principle that one should judge a speech by its audience and its
content is irrelevant. But to me Peikoff’s article ‘Fact and
Value’ was the most disturbing part of the exchange. It was not
just that he put words in Kelley’s mouth and was unfair in judging
him. There are probably many people who would agree with that. There
will probably be much said and written about it, so I shall, for the
most part, leave that subject for others. The most disturbing part of
Mr. Peikoff’s article was the illogical statements. He is the most
prominent living spokesman for Objectivism, a philosophy which is
committed to reason and logic. As such, I would expect from him a
more acute attention to logic.
I
considered calling this article “The All or Nothing Syndrome”,
which is an affliction of Mr. Peikoff’s. It refers to the tendency
to obliterate the distinction between “some” and “all” (or
between “none” and “some”), which is an extremely important
one in logic. There are several instances of it in Peikoff’s
article.
He
says, “In my judgment, Kelley’s paper is a repudiation of the
fundamental principles of Objectivism.” Kelley and Peikoff clearly
have different views about the relationship between fact and value.
But did Kelley repudiate “A is A”? Does disagreement on just one
principle imply disagreement on all of them?
He
argues for the principle: Every “is” implies an “ought”. Note
that the first word is “every”, not “some”. The word “every”
makes it an overstatement. It baffles me to hear that any trivial,
irrelevant fact implies an “ought.” There is the always
applicable one that I ought to regard it as a fact, but that is far
from the principle’s intended meaning.
He
claims that the good is a species of the true and that evil is a
species of the false. This is an apparently profound idea, so I did
not take it lightly. Consider the logic of this statement. It says if
X has the attribute “good”, then X necessarily also has the
attribute “true”, and that if X has the attribute “evil”,
then X necessarily also has the attribute “false”. I have a few
comments:
Some
X being both good and true does not imply that any X which is good is
also true; similarly for both evil and false.
Hitler
was evil. Would Peikoff also say he was “false”? If so, that is
bizarre.
It
implies there is no such thing as an evil truth. Is the fact that
Hitler and the Nazis murdered millions of people not an evil truth?
And Peikoff later gives examples of bad truths, such as too much
exposure to the sun is bad and getting caught in a tidal wave is bad,
which are inconsistent with the claim.
Similarly,
it implies there is no such thing as a good falsehood, for which a
counterexample easily comes to mind. Suppose A tells a lie to B to
protect C, where B has malicious intent and C is innocent of
wrongdoing.
It
is muddled. There are truths about what is good for us and about what
is bad for us. It is good for us to know these truths. There are
falsehoods about what is good for us and what is bad for us. It may
be or is (the right verb depends on the case) bad for us if we
believe these falsehoods. This makes sense, but it is far from what
he wrote.
I
checked Ayn Rand’s writing for an idea having any resemblance to it
and found nothing. And Peikoff exhorts the reader to not rewrite
Objectivism!
He
correctly paraphrases Kelley as saying: Truth and falsity apply
primarily to ideas, and good and evil primarily to actions. Note that
Kelley uses the word “primarily”, not “exclusively” or
“only”. Yet Peikoff launches an extended polemic as if Kelley
had said one of the latter. Admittedly Kelley gave a couple of poor
examples in discussing the subject. Kelley also failed to make it
clear that no dichotomy can be drawn between a man’s ideas and his
actions. But did Peikoff deliberately misrepresent Kelley to set up
his polemic? Or did he fail to note the logical import of the word
“primarily” means there are exceptions? Either way, it does not
speak well for Mr. Peikoff.
He
devotes a substantial part of his article to his ideas about the
connection between fact and value, between cognition and evaluation.
He summarizes his view in a single principle -- cognition implies
evaluation -- which he says is the main point of his article. In my
opinion, when he was writing this, he was so eager to railroad Kelley
that he let his emotions interfere with his reasoning and clear
communication. (Does this mean that his evaluation implied his
cognition?) This is a topic on which I have not spent sufficient time
to articulate well my own ideas, but I shall not let that stop me
from making a few comments:
I
found it difficult understanding clearly what he said and I attribute
it to his lack of clarification of key concepts. For example,
“evaluation” may mean a judgment about true/false or about
good/bad. Ayn Rand more than once said that to properly evaluate
what someone says or writes, look for the definitions. Well, I found
none in Peikoff’s exposition.
I
will presume that he meant by his principle something like this: one
should properly understand the phenomena or idea (Objectivist
epistemology), then decide whether it is good or bad based on one’s
understanding (and act accordingly). If this is even close, then I
believe he made a poor choice of words by using “imply”. This is
a term of logic and generally means the consequence follows
necessarily from the premise(s). But cognition and evaluation are
volitional, so evaluation is not a necessary, automatic consequence
of cognition. Cognition and evaluation can only be connected
logically by thinking, which is volitional.
Mr.
Peikoff said “every cognition implies an evaluation”, using
“evaluation” in the sense of good/bad. If he really believes
that, then I say his belief is seriously flawed. It would be a gross
overstatement. If the instance of cognition were one of learning a
new subject or idea and the knowledge gained were not instantaneously
integrated, it would be a gross mistake to make such an evaluation.
Facing reality and making good judgments also requires proper
recognition of one’s state of knowledge.
Now
imagine a person who believes that every cognition demands moral
evaluation and who is afflicted with the all-or-nothing syndrome.
That person would be overzealous to pass moral judgment and would do
so on a fragment of evidence, evading any evidence which would
indicate a different judgment.
Mr.
Peikoff may have impressed a few readers by pointing out the
contrapositive of his principle, i.e. that non-evaluation implies
non-cognition, but I saw it as a misuse of logic. One of my previous
comments was about the use of “imply” in this context. Another
pointed out an obvious counterexample to ‘all cognition implies
evaluation’. His contrapositive applied to that counterexample is:
If the person did not pass moral judgment, then the person learned
nothing!
Mr.
Peikoff tries to posit a much more extensive connection between
true/false and good/evil, between “is” and “ought”, and
between fact and value than can be reasonably substantiated. It was
both innovative and revolutionary for Ayn Rand to hold that there was
such a connection, considering that Hume and many later philosophers
held that there was absolutely no connection. However, the negation
of “none” is “some”, not “all”.
Peikoff
says “Kelley’s viewpoint is an explicit defense of a dichotomy
between fact and value, or between cognition and evaluation, and thus
between mind and body.” Here is misrepresentation and a non
sequitor in the same sentence! Kelley defended a difference or
distinction between fact and value, but hardly a dichotomy. Even if
Kelley had defended a dichotomy between cognition and evaluation, it
would be a dichotomy between two functions of mind, which clearly
would not imply a dichotomy between mind and body.
Mr.
Peikoff says, “a proper philosophy is an integrated whole, any
change in any element of which would destroy the entire system.” I
have two comments:
It
implies no one philosophical principle is stronger than any other. In
other words, every philosophical principle is equally important. I
find this notion totally contrary to Peikoff’s often repeated claim
that knowledge is hierarchical.
It
seems to say you either have it all right or none of it right. It is
another instance of the all-or-nothing syndrome.
He
did not discuss the Libertarians like Schwartz did, but he did say he
completely agreed with Schwartz, who is also much afflicted with the
all-or-nothing syndrome. An example is: Some Libertarians are
anarchist-subjectivists. They are morally reprehensible. Therefore,
any Libertarian is morally reprehensible.
Mr.
Peikoff’s all-or-nothing syndrome appears again in his closing
paragraphs. He tells readers, in effect, to agree with him totally or
disassociate themselves with Objectivism. This article makes me
wonder how Objectivism will flourish with him carrying the torch.
Logical flaws and the all-or-nothing syndrome make poor impressions.
The all-or-nothing syndrome may come in handy in polemics and
politics, but it is anti-logic and anti-reason. I believe it is
inappropriate for anyone who considers himself/herself to be
objective.
I
have made some strong criticisms of Mr. Peikoff here, so it seems
appropriate that my closing be tolerant, and I shall not pass
judgment on him solely on the basis of ‘Fact and Value’ and be
guilty of the all-or-nothing syndrome. I did agree with parts of his
description of Objectivism. I have appreciated his past lectures. I
shall probably be tolerant enough to buy his forthcoming book.
Thanks, Merlin. This is a good and thoughtful read.
ReplyDelete