We have been watching the film series, The Vietnam War, Episodes 1-5 the latest 5 days, Sun-Thu. There will be 5 more episodes Sun-Thu next week. They can be viewed on PBS's website shortly after they are aired on television. The whole series is 18 hours.
http://www.pbs.org/kenburns/the-vietnam-war/home/
I didn't care much for Episode 1, maybe because of the time span covered. But 2-5 have been excellent. I learned quite a bit from them, especially the USA inside politics the press didn't report at the time. LBJ was an awful human being. Yet he was funny with the colorful Texan language and idioms he used. I found some scenes unpleasant, even gruesome. I am amazed at some of the scenes captured by video cameras -- how somebody managed to be filming in those particular circumstances and Burns et al got and used their film. Episode 5's time frame ends just before the 1968 Tet Offensive. Having been there during that peak period of the war, the next episodes will be interesting.
Back in the USA, a coincidence occurred without my being aware of it at the time. I visited some friends in St. Louis about 2 weeks ago. I was headed home at the St. Louis airport, walking from the central part to the gate where my flight was to be. Walking toward me was Ken Burns. I didn't do anything to show that I recognized him. I didn't know then about the film series. If I had known, I probably would have said something to him and that I was a Vietnam vet.
Friday, September 22, 2017
Monday, September 18, 2017
Infinitesimal #4
A
intellectual war involving math and politics also occurred between
Thomas Hobbes and John Willis. Near the end of the English
Civil War (1642-1651) Hobbes wrote Leviathan.
In it Hobbes argued for a social contract and rule by an absolute
sovereign. He wrote that civil war and a brutal state of nature ("the
war of all against all") could only be avoided by strong,
undivided government.
Hobbes
also was a geometer of some repute. Similar to the Jesuits, he
believed that the answer to uncertaity and chaos was absolute
certainty and eternal order. They believed the key to both was
Euclidean geometry. He set about trying to "square the circle"
and solve two other long-standing geometry problems. "Square the
circle", or "quadrature the circle," means construct a
square with area exactly equal to the area of a given circle. (It can
be done with great, but not perfect, precision.) Under the
traditional restrictions of using only a compass and straight edge,
this had been proven impossible. Hobbes tried anyway. Mathematician
John Willis was well prepared to discredit any solution Hobbes
proposed. Willis' political attitudes also reflected the chaotic
years in England, but he believed in a state that would allow for a
plurality of views and wide scope for dissent. Willis also sided with
those who supported the use of infinitesimals.
Hobbes
was also a sharp critic of the mathematical works of Willis. For
Hobbes the infinitely small was an unwelcome intruder in mathematics.
In contrast Willis considered practically all the features of the
infinitely small to be clear advantages. His math was for
investigating the world as it is. The world could be a little
mysterious, unexplored, and ambiguous, but it invited new
investigation and new discovery (p. 287).
Friday, September 15, 2017
Infinitesimal #3
For centuries before the Reformation the Roman Catholic Church had reigned supreme in western Europe. Empires rose and fell. There had been invasions and occupations, heresies and plagues, but the Church had survived and thrived. The Church oversaw the lives of Europeans and gave order, meaning and purpose to their existence, and ruled on everything from the date of Easter to the motion of Earth and much else (p. 24). The Reformation was a challenge to all that.
The Jesuits, formed in 1540, were not much interested in mathematics in their first few decades. The founder, St. Ignatius, had little interest in mathematics. But as they built their education system, they became committed to Euclidean geometry. "It was the core of their teaching and the foundation of their mathematical practice. ... [T]he whole point of studying and teaching mathematics was that it demonstrated how universal truth imposed itself upon the world -- rationally, hierarchically, and inescapably. Ideally, the Jesuits believed, the truths of religion would be imposed on the world just like geometrical theorems, leaving no room for avoidance or denial by Protestants or other heretics and leading to the ultimate triumph of the Church. For the Jesuits, mathematics must be studied according to the principles and procedures of Euclid, or it should not be studied at all. A mathematics that ran counter to these practices not only was useless to their purposes, but it would challenge their unconquerable faith that truth, handed down through the hierarchy of the universal catholic Church, would inevitably prevail" (p. 74). Infinitesimals are not part of Euclid's Elements.
"The Jesuits valued mathematics for the strict rational order it imposed on an unruly universe. Mathematics, particularly Euclidean, represented the triumph of mind over matter and reason over the untamed material world, and reflected the Jesuit ideal not only in mathematics but also in religious and even political matters" (p. 91).
"Euclidean geometry was the embodiment of order. Its demonstrations began with the universal self-evident assumptions, and then proceed step by logical step to describe fixed and necessary relations between geometrical objects: the sum of the angles in a triangle is always equal to two right angles ... These relations are absolute, and cannot be denied by any rational being" (p. 119). A group of five Jesuits, the Rectors, had a strong control over what was taught, and it issued prohibitions on the teaching and promotion of infinitesimals (p. 122).
Cavalieri's and Galileo's ideas ran counter to that. They held that lines were comprised of indivisible points, planes of indivisible lines, and solids of indivisible planes. Thus these geometrical objects were little different from the material objects we see around us (p. 91). Instead of mathematical reason imposing order on the physical world, pure mathematical objects are created in the image of physical ones. They wanted to study the world and find the order within. They were willing to accept some ambiguity and even paradox as long as it led to a deeper understanding (p. 177).
In Discourses (or Two New Sciences) Galileo made use of Aristotle's wheel paradox (link) to arrive "at a radical and paradoxical conclusion: a continuous line is composed of an infinite number of indivisible points separated by an infinite number of minuscule empty spaces. This supported both his theory of the structure of matter and his view that material objects are held together by the vacuum that pervades them" (p. 89-91). How Galileo thought about the wheel paradox is described here.
The Jesuits, formed in 1540, were not much interested in mathematics in their first few decades. The founder, St. Ignatius, had little interest in mathematics. But as they built their education system, they became committed to Euclidean geometry. "It was the core of their teaching and the foundation of their mathematical practice. ... [T]he whole point of studying and teaching mathematics was that it demonstrated how universal truth imposed itself upon the world -- rationally, hierarchically, and inescapably. Ideally, the Jesuits believed, the truths of religion would be imposed on the world just like geometrical theorems, leaving no room for avoidance or denial by Protestants or other heretics and leading to the ultimate triumph of the Church. For the Jesuits, mathematics must be studied according to the principles and procedures of Euclid, or it should not be studied at all. A mathematics that ran counter to these practices not only was useless to their purposes, but it would challenge their unconquerable faith that truth, handed down through the hierarchy of the universal catholic Church, would inevitably prevail" (p. 74). Infinitesimals are not part of Euclid's Elements.
"The Jesuits valued mathematics for the strict rational order it imposed on an unruly universe. Mathematics, particularly Euclidean, represented the triumph of mind over matter and reason over the untamed material world, and reflected the Jesuit ideal not only in mathematics but also in religious and even political matters" (p. 91).
"Euclidean geometry was the embodiment of order. Its demonstrations began with the universal self-evident assumptions, and then proceed step by logical step to describe fixed and necessary relations between geometrical objects: the sum of the angles in a triangle is always equal to two right angles ... These relations are absolute, and cannot be denied by any rational being" (p. 119). A group of five Jesuits, the Rectors, had a strong control over what was taught, and it issued prohibitions on the teaching and promotion of infinitesimals (p. 122).
Cavalieri's and Galileo's ideas ran counter to that. They held that lines were comprised of indivisible points, planes of indivisible lines, and solids of indivisible planes. Thus these geometrical objects were little different from the material objects we see around us (p. 91). Instead of mathematical reason imposing order on the physical world, pure mathematical objects are created in the image of physical ones. They wanted to study the world and find the order within. They were willing to accept some ambiguity and even paradox as long as it led to a deeper understanding (p. 177).
In Discourses (or Two New Sciences) Galileo made use of Aristotle's wheel paradox (link) to arrive "at a radical and paradoxical conclusion: a continuous line is composed of an infinite number of indivisible points separated by an infinite number of minuscule empty spaces. This supported both his theory of the structure of matter and his view that material objects are held together by the vacuum that pervades them" (p. 89-91). How Galileo thought about the wheel paradox is described here.
Tuesday, September 12, 2017
Infinitesimal #2
What are infinitesimals? That term was coined around 1670. A related term is indivisibles. The author of Infinitesimal says: "To understand why the struggle over indivisibles became so critical, we need to take a close look at the concept itself, which appears deceptively simple but is in fact deeply problematic. In its simplest form the doctrine states that every line is composed of a string of points, or "indivisibles," which are the line's building blocks, and which cannot themselves be divided" (p. 8-9).
Some mathematicians, especially Cavalieri, held that a line is composed of an "infinite" number of points, a plane is composed of an "infinite" number of lines laid parallel and a solid is composed of an "infinite" number of planes laid parallel. Of course, for any polygon, sets of parallel lines can be drawn in different directions, e.g. vertical or horizontal or diagonal, which gives a different number of lines.
Infinitesimal mentions that the math symbol used for infinity, ∞, was invented by John Wallis (who has a prominent role in the book). Wikipedia confirms this. Wallis used 1/∞ for an infinitesimal.
One conundrum is how many indivisibles (or points) there are in a given line and how small they are. Assume a given line has a huge, yet finite, number, we can call a gazillion. That suggests each indivisible is 1/gazillion in size. Problems start arising when considering other lines of different length. A "deep" problem -- discovered by the Greeks -- is that some lines can not be subdivided into an integer number of uniform-sized units, no matter how small they are. For example, the square root of two length units (e.g. inches) cannot be converted to an integer number of anything, because the square root of two is an irrational number. Ditto for pi, the circumference of a circle with a diameter of 1 length unit, and Euler's number e, the base base of natural logarithms.
A related topic is the continuum. The usual meaning of continuous is “unbroken” or “uninterrupted.” Thus a continuous entity—a continuum—has no “gaps.” Aristotle addressed it in book 6 of his Physics. He concluded that the concept of infinitesimals was erroneous, and that continuous magnitudes can be divided ad infinitum (p. 10). The Jesuit Benito Pereia proposed the thesis that a line is composed of separate points and presented all the arguments in its favor by others. He then demolished them one by one, and concluded, like Aristotle, that the continuum is infinitely divisible, and not composed of indivisibles (p. 121). The Jesuits thought Cavalieri's were untenable.
The Epilogue of Infinitesimal describes how the use of "infinitesimals" later grew to have a prominent part of mathematics. I believe it would have been improved if it explained the concept of a limit as used in math, such as in calculus. Said concept was developed in the 19th century. It involves, but is not identical to, "infinitesimals" as described in the book. The similarity is stronger in integral calculus.
A much longer history of infinitesimals and related topics is here. The historical period the book is mainly about is a very small part of it.
Some mathematicians, especially Cavalieri, held that a line is composed of an "infinite" number of points, a plane is composed of an "infinite" number of lines laid parallel and a solid is composed of an "infinite" number of planes laid parallel. Of course, for any polygon, sets of parallel lines can be drawn in different directions, e.g. vertical or horizontal or diagonal, which gives a different number of lines.
Infinitesimal mentions that the math symbol used for infinity, ∞, was invented by John Wallis (who has a prominent role in the book). Wikipedia confirms this. Wallis used 1/∞ for an infinitesimal.
One conundrum is how many indivisibles (or points) there are in a given line and how small they are. Assume a given line has a huge, yet finite, number, we can call a gazillion. That suggests each indivisible is 1/gazillion in size. Problems start arising when considering other lines of different length. A "deep" problem -- discovered by the Greeks -- is that some lines can not be subdivided into an integer number of uniform-sized units, no matter how small they are. For example, the square root of two length units (e.g. inches) cannot be converted to an integer number of anything, because the square root of two is an irrational number. Ditto for pi, the circumference of a circle with a diameter of 1 length unit, and Euler's number e, the base base of natural logarithms.
A related topic is the continuum. The usual meaning of continuous is “unbroken” or “uninterrupted.” Thus a continuous entity—a continuum—has no “gaps.” Aristotle addressed it in book 6 of his Physics. He concluded that the concept of infinitesimals was erroneous, and that continuous magnitudes can be divided ad infinitum (p. 10). The Jesuit Benito Pereia proposed the thesis that a line is composed of separate points and presented all the arguments in its favor by others. He then demolished them one by one, and concluded, like Aristotle, that the continuum is infinitely divisible, and not composed of indivisibles (p. 121). The Jesuits thought Cavalieri's were untenable.
The Epilogue of Infinitesimal describes how the use of "infinitesimals" later grew to have a prominent part of mathematics. I believe it would have been improved if it explained the concept of a limit as used in math, such as in calculus. Said concept was developed in the 19th century. It involves, but is not identical to, "infinitesimals" as described in the book. The similarity is stronger in integral calculus.
A much longer history of infinitesimals and related topics is here. The historical period the book is mainly about is a very small part of it.
Saturday, September 9, 2017
Infinitesimal #1
I
read the book Infinitesimal: How A Dangerous Mathematical Theory Shaped The Modern World.
In mathematics, infinitesimals are things so small that there is no
way to measure them. I thought the history in Infinitesimal
– both political-religious and mathematics from about 1500 to 1675
– was very interesting. I believe the author makes the tie between
them stronger than what they actually were, but there were parallel
ideas - parties opposing one another in two very different realms.
The
Society of Jesus, more commonly called the Jesuits, has a prominent
role. Before Martin Luther initiated the Protestant Reformation, the
Catholic Church was the dominant power in society. Kings and their
lower ranking brethren depended on approval by the Catholic clergy.
The anti-Reformists believed that the Reformation would bring
about disorder and war. The Jesuits became the leading defenders of
Catholicism. In large part their success was due to their building of
educational institutions.
A
leading Jesuit, Christopher
Clavius, was almost
single-handedly responsible for the adoption of a rigorous
mathematics curriculum – Euclidean based -- in an age where
mathematics was often ridiculed by philosophers and religious
authorities. While Clavius clearly opposed the heliocentric model of
Copernicus, it was mainly other Jesuits who opposed infinitesimals.
A
leading proponent of infinitesimals
was mathematician Bonaventura
Cavalieri. He was a Jesuat, which is different from a Jesuit.
Except
as noted below, the author summarizes the book's thesis very well as
follows.
"Why
did the best minds of the early modern world fight so fiercely over
the infinitely small? The reason was that much more was at stake than
an obscure mathematical concept. The fight was over the face of the
modern world. Two camps confronted each other over the infinitesmal.
On the one side were ranged the forces of heirarchy and order –
Jesuits, Hobbesians, French royal courtiers, and High Chuch
Anglicans. They believed in a unified and fixed order in the world,
both natural and human, and were fiercely opposed to infinitesmals.
On the other side were comparative "liberalizers" such as
Galileo, [John] Wallis, and the Newtonians. They believed in a more
pluralistic and flexible order, one that might accommodate a range of
views and diverse centers of power, and championed infinitesmals and
their use in mathematics. The lines were drawn, and a victory for one
side or the other would leave its imprint on the world for centuries
to come" (p. 8).
Most
of the history presented in the book happened before Isaac Newton
published his revolutionary Principia in 1687,
so Cavalieri instead of "the Newtonians" arguably fits
better.
Tuesday, September 5, 2017
The Cost of Rights
In
my August 27 post I said Passions and Constraint was unclear about
where the author stood on controversial
rights and how far government can go to reach its goals. I said
maybe his answer is in another book, ,
co-authored with Cass Sunstein.
It wasn't there.
The Introduction holds that there are two kinds of rights – moral rights and legal rights. It has little to say about moral rights and says they are "toothless by definition." There is nothing about natural rights along the lines of John Locke. In contrast legal rights have "teeth." They are defined and enforced by governments. The authors claim that legally enforcing rights costs money, but this is "ignored by almost everyone." Really? Is almost everyone ignorant of total government spending is now about 36% of GDP, was 41% in 2009, and 40% in 2010-11? Is almost everyone ignorant about taxes?
The
authors continually confound rights with enforcement of rights.
Chapter 1 claims that all
rights are positive, and that the common distinction between negative rights
and positive rights is inadequate because “all legally enforced
rights are necessarily positive rights.” Usually negative
rights are meant to prohibit what others can do to you. Positive
rights are meant to require actions by others on your behalf. They
portray the views of others correctly: “Negative rights ban and
exclude government; positive ones invite and demand government.”
“Negative rights protect liberty; positive rights typically promote
equality.” However, these and others are only “storybook
distinctions” in the authors’ opinion (p. 41). They belittle the
difference between rights as limiting the actions of government and
limiting the actions between private persons. Co-author Holmes in
Passions and Constraint wrote about factions and the Founding
Fathers’ great concern about the encroachment of government on the
rights of citizen. The book says nothing about Founding Fathers,
Madison, or Jefferson.
As I expected, the authors
laud welfare rights as they construe them. The
Cost of Rights
reads like a puff piece for Progressivism. I was not surprised to
find more 1-star reviews than 5-star reviews on Amazon.
Friday, September 1, 2017
On Peikoff's ‘Fact and Value’
I wrote the following 28 years ago. At that time I gave copies to a few people, but did not publish it. The forthcoming book referred to in the last paragraph is Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand. 'Fact and Value' had the lead role in the Objectivist schism of 1989. Most other comments about the schism have been about whether Objectivism is closed or open, or about sanctioning. I considered that a mere "turf war" then, and still do.
ON
PEIKOFF’S ‘FACT AND VALUE’
by
Merlin Jetton July 27, 1989
The
series of articles by Peter Schwartz, David Kelley, and Leonard
Peikoff was both interesting and disappointing to read. It amazes me
that such a heated exchange could arise from the mere event of David
Kelley making a speech.
I
have come to expect such behavior from Schwartz. He has a history of
making straw men and burning them. He sometimes makes bizarre
judgments. He did that in this instance, operating under the
principle that one should judge a speech by its audience and its
content is irrelevant. But to me Peikoff’s article ‘Fact and
Value’ was the most disturbing part of the exchange. It was not
just that he put words in Kelley’s mouth and was unfair in judging
him. There are probably many people who would agree with that. There
will probably be much said and written about it, so I shall, for the
most part, leave that subject for others. The most disturbing part of
Mr. Peikoff’s article was the illogical statements. He is the most
prominent living spokesman for Objectivism, a philosophy which is
committed to reason and logic. As such, I would expect from him a
more acute attention to logic.
I
considered calling this article “The All or Nothing Syndrome”,
which is an affliction of Mr. Peikoff’s. It refers to the tendency
to obliterate the distinction between “some” and “all” (or
between “none” and “some”), which is an extremely important
one in logic. There are several instances of it in Peikoff’s
article.
He
says, “In my judgment, Kelley’s paper is a repudiation of the
fundamental principles of Objectivism.” Kelley and Peikoff clearly
have different views about the relationship between fact and value.
But did Kelley repudiate “A is A”? Does disagreement on just one
principle imply disagreement on all of them?
He
argues for the principle: Every “is” implies an “ought”. Note
that the first word is “every”, not “some”. The word “every”
makes it an overstatement. It baffles me to hear that any trivial,
irrelevant fact implies an “ought.” There is the always
applicable one that I ought to regard it as a fact, but that is far
from the principle’s intended meaning.
He
claims that the good is a species of the true and that evil is a
species of the false. This is an apparently profound idea, so I did
not take it lightly. Consider the logic of this statement. It says if
X has the attribute “good”, then X necessarily also has the
attribute “true”, and that if X has the attribute “evil”,
then X necessarily also has the attribute “false”. I have a few
comments:
Some
X being both good and true does not imply that any X which is good is
also true; similarly for both evil and false.
Hitler
was evil. Would Peikoff also say he was “false”? If so, that is
bizarre.
It
implies there is no such thing as an evil truth. Is the fact that
Hitler and the Nazis murdered millions of people not an evil truth?
And Peikoff later gives examples of bad truths, such as too much
exposure to the sun is bad and getting caught in a tidal wave is bad,
which are inconsistent with the claim.
Similarly,
it implies there is no such thing as a good falsehood, for which a
counterexample easily comes to mind. Suppose A tells a lie to B to
protect C, where B has malicious intent and C is innocent of
wrongdoing.
It
is muddled. There are truths about what is good for us and about what
is bad for us. It is good for us to know these truths. There are
falsehoods about what is good for us and what is bad for us. It may
be or is (the right verb depends on the case) bad for us if we
believe these falsehoods. This makes sense, but it is far from what
he wrote.
I
checked Ayn Rand’s writing for an idea having any resemblance to it
and found nothing. And Peikoff exhorts the reader to not rewrite
Objectivism!
He
correctly paraphrases Kelley as saying: Truth and falsity apply
primarily to ideas, and good and evil primarily to actions. Note that
Kelley uses the word “primarily”, not “exclusively” or
“only”. Yet Peikoff launches an extended polemic as if Kelley
had said one of the latter. Admittedly Kelley gave a couple of poor
examples in discussing the subject. Kelley also failed to make it
clear that no dichotomy can be drawn between a man’s ideas and his
actions. But did Peikoff deliberately misrepresent Kelley to set up
his polemic? Or did he fail to note the logical import of the word
“primarily” means there are exceptions? Either way, it does not
speak well for Mr. Peikoff.
He
devotes a substantial part of his article to his ideas about the
connection between fact and value, between cognition and evaluation.
He summarizes his view in a single principle -- cognition implies
evaluation -- which he says is the main point of his article. In my
opinion, when he was writing this, he was so eager to railroad Kelley
that he let his emotions interfere with his reasoning and clear
communication. (Does this mean that his evaluation implied his
cognition?) This is a topic on which I have not spent sufficient time
to articulate well my own ideas, but I shall not let that stop me
from making a few comments:
I
found it difficult understanding clearly what he said and I attribute
it to his lack of clarification of key concepts. For example,
“evaluation” may mean a judgment about true/false or about
good/bad. Ayn Rand more than once said that to properly evaluate
what someone says or writes, look for the definitions. Well, I found
none in Peikoff’s exposition.
I
will presume that he meant by his principle something like this: one
should properly understand the phenomena or idea (Objectivist
epistemology), then decide whether it is good or bad based on one’s
understanding (and act accordingly). If this is even close, then I
believe he made a poor choice of words by using “imply”. This is
a term of logic and generally means the consequence follows
necessarily from the premise(s). But cognition and evaluation are
volitional, so evaluation is not a necessary, automatic consequence
of cognition. Cognition and evaluation can only be connected
logically by thinking, which is volitional.
Mr.
Peikoff said “every cognition implies an evaluation”, using
“evaluation” in the sense of good/bad. If he really believes
that, then I say his belief is seriously flawed. It would be a gross
overstatement. If the instance of cognition were one of learning a
new subject or idea and the knowledge gained were not instantaneously
integrated, it would be a gross mistake to make such an evaluation.
Facing reality and making good judgments also requires proper
recognition of one’s state of knowledge.
Now
imagine a person who believes that every cognition demands moral
evaluation and who is afflicted with the all-or-nothing syndrome.
That person would be overzealous to pass moral judgment and would do
so on a fragment of evidence, evading any evidence which would
indicate a different judgment.
Mr.
Peikoff may have impressed a few readers by pointing out the
contrapositive of his principle, i.e. that non-evaluation implies
non-cognition, but I saw it as a misuse of logic. One of my previous
comments was about the use of “imply” in this context. Another
pointed out an obvious counterexample to ‘all cognition implies
evaluation’. His contrapositive applied to that counterexample is:
If the person did not pass moral judgment, then the person learned
nothing!
Mr.
Peikoff tries to posit a much more extensive connection between
true/false and good/evil, between “is” and “ought”, and
between fact and value than can be reasonably substantiated. It was
both innovative and revolutionary for Ayn Rand to hold that there was
such a connection, considering that Hume and many later philosophers
held that there was absolutely no connection. However, the negation
of “none” is “some”, not “all”.
Peikoff
says “Kelley’s viewpoint is an explicit defense of a dichotomy
between fact and value, or between cognition and evaluation, and thus
between mind and body.” Here is misrepresentation and a non
sequitor in the same sentence! Kelley defended a difference or
distinction between fact and value, but hardly a dichotomy. Even if
Kelley had defended a dichotomy between cognition and evaluation, it
would be a dichotomy between two functions of mind, which clearly
would not imply a dichotomy between mind and body.
Mr.
Peikoff says, “a proper philosophy is an integrated whole, any
change in any element of which would destroy the entire system.” I
have two comments:
It
implies no one philosophical principle is stronger than any other. In
other words, every philosophical principle is equally important. I
find this notion totally contrary to Peikoff’s often repeated claim
that knowledge is hierarchical.
It
seems to say you either have it all right or none of it right. It is
another instance of the all-or-nothing syndrome.
He
did not discuss the Libertarians like Schwartz did, but he did say he
completely agreed with Schwartz, who is also much afflicted with the
all-or-nothing syndrome. An example is: Some Libertarians are
anarchist-subjectivists. They are morally reprehensible. Therefore,
any Libertarian is morally reprehensible.
Mr.
Peikoff’s all-or-nothing syndrome appears again in his closing
paragraphs. He tells readers, in effect, to agree with him totally or
disassociate themselves with Objectivism. This article makes me
wonder how Objectivism will flourish with him carrying the torch.
Logical flaws and the all-or-nothing syndrome make poor impressions.
The all-or-nothing syndrome may come in handy in polemics and
politics, but it is anti-logic and anti-reason. I believe it is
inappropriate for anyone who considers himself/herself to be
objective.
I
have made some strong criticisms of Mr. Peikoff here, so it seems
appropriate that my closing be tolerant, and I shall not pass
judgment on him solely on the basis of ‘Fact and Value’ and be
guilty of the all-or-nothing syndrome. I did agree with parts of his
description of Objectivism. I have appreciated his past lectures. I
shall probably be tolerant enough to buy his forthcoming book.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)