The root of this article is part of the book review of After Capitalism that I wrote for
Amazon. Inspired by Karl Marx and the labor theory of value, the author
criticizes what he calls passive capitalists, those who derive income – interest,
dividends, profits -- from work that they don’t partake in. He bases his argument on the labor theory of
value (LTV).
Classical economists, the main ones being Adam Smith and
David Riccardo, subscribed to the LTV to some extent. It’s obvious that labor
does create things of value, but the classical economists also attributed value
to land and capital.
Marx would have nothing of that and attributed all value
to labor. Producing value from land requires some labor. Even the value of capital goods is all attributed to past labor. The
author of After Capitalism also
attributes all value to labor. However, his arguments and examples do not
address different kinds of labor. He
gives an example of workers growing corn, assuming the land is of uniform
quality and the workers are all equally skilled. He doesn't say the workers do
different kinds of work, like planting versus harvesting, so presumably they
all do the same work.
Marx extended the LTV with notions of ‘abstract’
labor and ‘socially necessary’ labor. The former abstracts from the particular
characteristics of all of the labor and is akin to an average, homogeneous labor. It
was ‘abstraction run amok’ in my view. But it allowed him to side-step having
to address different kinds of labor and different degrees of skill and
efficiency, as did the author of After
Capitalism.
This and the next two paragraphs are taken from my book
review. Suppose the following. An
entrepreneurial builder (EB) wants to build a house. He estimates the total
cost, including laborers and an architect who will be paid and interest to be
paid after selling the house, to be
$100,000. EB has only $20,000. Architecture documents and building materials
and buying the land will cost $50,000, so he will borrow $30,000. The house is
built and he sells it for, say, $125,000. He pays off the loan and interest of
$31,000, leaving $94,000. How should the $94,000 be allocated between EB, the
architect, excavators, carpenters, roofers, electricians, plumbers, concrete
guys, etc.? (Presumably EB has first dibs for $50,000.) The LTV offers no answer. It attributes all value
to labor, but doesn't answer this
allocation question. Basing it on hours worked ignoring skills, quality,
efficiency, etc. is absurd. The best it could do is look at market prices for
these various kinds of work and allocate on that basis, but Marxist theory
holds that market price and value are two very different things.
Hold on. Where is EB going to find all these workers who
will wait to be paid until after the
house is sold for an indeterminate
amount? Being realistic, each will want payment as soon as his/her work is done
at a rate or amount agreed to in advance, not some distant, indeterminate
amount. Nor does each laborer desire to later argue with the rest and EB about
what a fair distribution is. Alternatively, if laborers want paid as soon as
his/her work is done, EB will need to borrow even more money and pay more interest.
The capitalist-lender can save the day, and the project can proceed. Yet Schweickart asserts an entrepreneur
like EB needs only the labor of others, and not money. Hmm, how will the workers be paid?
We could refine the example, saying that the $20,000 EB
starts with was half provided by a passive capitalist, who will share in half
the money that's left, if any, at the end of the project after a reasonable cut
for EB's work on the project.
The author does see value in entrepreneurial work -- EB's is only one example -- but his analysis of capitalism fails to recognize that passive capitalists
advance money to labor long before work is done and often wait to be paid when
the workers' product is eventually sold. After
Capitalism portrays passive capitalist income as entirely unjustified. It also
claims savings and lending have "no direct effect on production" and
production doesn't need savings.
The example could also be altered to assume that some or
all the workers on the project combined have enough savings and willingness to
lend the $30,000 to EB. Does that alter the analysis? It does very little in my
view. Regarding the loan, they would be passive capitalists like a bank would
be. Workers and passive capitalists being the same people should not matter.
The functions remain separable. Qua workers their role on the project is no
different. They might, however, be a little more diligent since they have a
little more at stake on the success of the project. If they were to loan the
money to EB at an interest rate set in advance, the dollars of interest are the
same, barring the project going bad and EB defaulting.
On the other hand, suppose the workers supplied the
$10,000 instead of the passive partner capitalist described above. Then the
workers could have a greater stake in seeing how successful the project is, since the payoff to them is directly
connected to the sale price of the house. They would be taking on some risk
(uncertainty).
Let us return to the first two scenarios described. The
first one in which EB doesn’t borrow from the bank and the workers are not paid
until after the house is sold, I will call the “no passive capitalist” (NPC)
scenario. The second one in which EB borrows from the bank and pays each worker
as soon as his or her work is done at a preset rate or amount, I shall call the
“passive capitalist” (PC) scenario.
Incidentally, After Capitalism doesn’t
use the term, but EB could be called an “active capitalist,” an obvious
contrast to “passive capitalist.”
After
Capitalism grants value to an entrepreneur’s labor, management, and creativity.
On the other hand, it says that a passive investor gains only at the expense of
the people who produce the goods and services, by expropriating “surplus value”
(p. 39), the favorite Marxist idea. He ridicules the idea that passive capitalists
take any risk. For passive capitalists risk is a mere cover-up for
expropriating “surplus value” from workers.
Let us compare the NPC and PC scenarios. If the house is
sold near or above the price expected by EB, then in retrospect it’s easy to
assume that the bank took no risk. However, the view at the time the loan is
made is very different. What if the project fails and EB defaults on paying
some or even all of the loan plus interest? In the PC scenario, the workers
assume no risk for the project’s outcome. In the NPC scenario, they have
significant risk. Remuneration for their work highly depends on the sale price
of the finished house. Hence, one could argue that the workers’ risk in the NPC
is transformed by the passive capitalist into the passive capitalist’s risk in
the PC scenario. Arguing that the workers are merely expropriated is akin to
arguing that workers are entitled to free insurance! Indeed, the passive
capitalist has something in common with an insurer. It collects a “premium” in
the form of interest, while it loses much more if disaster strikes. If a
passive capitalist were to provide money that enables a project that employs
workers, and is denied any interest, then who is exploiting whom?