Chapter
4 is about higher-level concepts. First level concepts are formed
directly from perception. Following Rand, higher-level concepts are
formed by "abstraction from abstractions." For example, furniture is formed from the prior first-level concepts
table,
bed,
chair,
etc. The higher-level concept is a wider integration.
Binswanger
contrasts his and Rand's view from that of Realists. The Realist
"model implies that wider concepts have less cognitive content
than the narrower ones from which they were formed. For the Realists,
"table" abstracts the "universal" from individual
tables by mentally subtracting away and discarding everything that
differs among tables. Then, "furniture" discards even more"
(141). In contrast "Rand's theory recognizes that
concept-formation is integrative, which means that the wider concept
contains more cognitive content than any of the narrower ones from
which it was formed" (141).
His portrayal of the Realist view seems biased. He uses "subtract"
and "discard" rather than "ignore" or "neglect." "For Realists, reaching a more abstract level means having a narrower "insight" into a universal embedded inside a given universal -- the "furniturehood" lurking inside of "tableness" and "bedness." For Realists, the wider concept, the emptier of cognitive content" (141).
He says Rand's theory attributes more cognitive content to higher-level concepts. However, "more cognitive content" is ambiguous. Does it mean more units subsumed or a wider range of attributes? He says little or nothing about the former and sides with the latter. Clearly furniture subsumes more units (things or referents) than does chair. Based on more units subsumed, the Realist view adds rather than subtracts or discards. Of course, the criteria of inclusion into the higher level concept is less strict for the Realist view, and it is likewise for Rand's theory. For example, the criteria of inclusion for furniture is less strict than for chair. One criteria for chair, but not furniture, is that its purpose is for sitting, a criteria not met by table, dresser, etc., which have other purposes.
While I agree with his portraying the Realist view as pursuing an "elusive phantom", I regard it as somewhat less mystical than he. What is elusive in the Realist view is the pursuit of something which is precisely identical in each instance or unit of the concept. In his and Rand's view the pursuit is of similarity. The ramifications of that difference are monumental. I give a hat tip to Peter Abelard.
Is the Realist view that there is something precisely identical in each instance amiss for all concepts? I don't believe so. I believe numbers qualify, for example, the number 2 abstracted from all instances of pairs.
Some sort of "intuition" or "insight" is required for the pursuit of similarity of higher-level concepts. In his final chapter Binswanger writes about the concepts inertia, natural selection, and germ. In my view the developers of these concepts had some sort of extraordinary capacity, which for lack of a better term I call "intuition" or "insight." They grasped the similarity that other people had not.
Returning to his text, the second type of higher-level concept consists of subdivisions or "narrowings" of existing concepts. "Narrowings have virtually never been discussed in the history of epistemology" (142). That agrees with my experience.
"There are two ways of subdividing an earlier concept: 1) by narrowing the earlier concept's measuring range, or 2) by adding a new characteristic, a characteristic not used in forming the earlier concept" (142).
He says Rand's theory attributes more cognitive content to higher-level concepts. However, "more cognitive content" is ambiguous. Does it mean more units subsumed or a wider range of attributes? He says little or nothing about the former and sides with the latter. Clearly furniture subsumes more units (things or referents) than does chair. Based on more units subsumed, the Realist view adds rather than subtracts or discards. Of course, the criteria of inclusion into the higher level concept is less strict for the Realist view, and it is likewise for Rand's theory. For example, the criteria of inclusion for furniture is less strict than for chair. One criteria for chair, but not furniture, is that its purpose is for sitting, a criteria not met by table, dresser, etc., which have other purposes.
While I agree with his portraying the Realist view as pursuing an "elusive phantom", I regard it as somewhat less mystical than he. What is elusive in the Realist view is the pursuit of something which is precisely identical in each instance or unit of the concept. In his and Rand's view the pursuit is of similarity. The ramifications of that difference are monumental. I give a hat tip to Peter Abelard.
Is the Realist view that there is something precisely identical in each instance amiss for all concepts? I don't believe so. I believe numbers qualify, for example, the number 2 abstracted from all instances of pairs.
Some sort of "intuition" or "insight" is required for the pursuit of similarity of higher-level concepts. In his final chapter Binswanger writes about the concepts inertia, natural selection, and germ. In my view the developers of these concepts had some sort of extraordinary capacity, which for lack of a better term I call "intuition" or "insight." They grasped the similarity that other people had not.
Returning to his text, the second type of higher-level concept consists of subdivisions or "narrowings" of existing concepts. "Narrowings have virtually never been discussed in the history of epistemology" (142). That agrees with my experience.
"There are two ways of subdividing an earlier concept: 1) by narrowing the earlier concept's measuring range, or 2) by adding a new characteristic, a characteristic not used in forming the earlier concept" (142).
Merlin, in connection with this part, I imagine you would find stimulating the latest installment of my coverage of Leonard Peikoff's 1964 Phd dissertation. I connect his work back then to the latest scholarship in his topics today, both to recent historical scholarship on the classical philosophers on his topics and to recent Objectivist scholarship. That includes classification (and criteria) of theories of universals and concepts. I touch on Binswanger there also, in an important endnote on these classifications. (I'll try to link to this latest installment of my work on LP's '64, but if that is unsuccessful, just go to the site Objectivism Online, where you will find it. It's gotten over a hundred reads these three days its been up, and that's pretty good. Also, on the sociological side, you might like to see what has transpired on this at the current post on my Timeline on FB.) http://forum.objectivismonline.com/index.php?/topic/30587-peikoffs-dissertation/&tab=comments#comment-352374
ReplyDelete